Next Article in Journal
Stochastic and Self-Organisation Patterns in a 17-Year PM10 Time Series in Athens, Greece
Previous Article in Journal
Transient Dynamics in the Random Growth and Reset Model
Previous Article in Special Issue
An ESR Framework for the Study of Consciousness
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

A Compositional Model of Consciousness Based on Consciousness-Only

1
Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford, 15 Parks Rd., Oxford OX1 3QD, UK
2
Cognitive Neuroimaging Unit, INSERM U992, NeuroSpin, 91191 Gif-sur-Yvette, France
3
Cambridge Quantum Computing Ltd., Cambridge CB2 1UB, UK
4
St Edmund’s College, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB3 0BN, UK
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Submission received: 7 August 2020 / Revised: 20 February 2021 / Accepted: 24 February 2021 / Published: 5 March 2021
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Models of Consciousness)

Abstract

:
Scientific studies of consciousness rely on objects whose existence is assumed to be independent of any consciousness. On the contrary, we assume consciousness to be fundamental, and that one of the main features of consciousness is characterized as being other-dependent. We set up a framework which naturally subsumes this feature by defining a compact closed category where morphisms represent conscious processes. These morphisms are a composition of a set of generators, each being specified by their relations with other generators, and therefore co-dependent. The framework is general enough and fits well into a compositional model of consciousness. Interestingly, we also show how our proposal may become a step towards avoiding the hard problem of consciousness, and thereby address the combination problem of conscious experiences.

1. Introduction

Despite scientific advances in understanding the objective neural correlates of consciousness [1], science has so far failed in recovering subjective features from objective and measurable correlates of consciousness. One example is the unity of consciousness. According to the phenomenology of consciousness [2,3], one of the most salient features of conscious experience is its unity: “any set of conscious states of a subject at a time is unified...by being aspects of a single encompassing state of consciousness” [3]. If someone experiences colour and noise, the experience of colour is not followed by the experience of noise separately, even though it might be sequential, but both are experienced together as different aspects/content of one single conscious experience. Current models postpone the explanation of that unity, assuming there will be further developments [4]. In the meantime, they reduce conscious experience to neural events.
In this article, we present an alternative approach: consciousness as a fundamental process of nature. Our approach takes inspiration from the Yogacara school [5,6], conscious agents model [7] and phenomenology [8,9]. In our framework, subjectivity, a key feature of consciousness is characterised as other-dependent, also called co-dependent, i.e., the nature of existence arising from causes and conditions that are interdependent between each other. Without falling into idealism or dualism, we propose that consciousness should be treated as a primary process.
To model the co-dependent nature, we propose a compositional model for consciousness. This model is based on symmetric monoidal categories (Section 2), a.k.a Process Theory [10,11]. At the core of process theory lies the principle of compositionality (Section 3). Compositionality defines the whole as compositions of the parts. These parts, however, are not trivial decompositions, they contain in themselves the very properties that define the whole (in our case, conscious processes compound other conscious processes). Parts and the whole are therefore defined together, they co-depend. Compositionality is thus a middle ground between reductionism and holism [12]. This makes process theory and our compositional framework suitable for investigating the irreducible structural properties of conscious experience [13].
Finally, our framework intends to mathematize a few aspects of the phenomenology of conscious experience (Section 4) and target its major questions [14,15]. For instance, the unity of consciousness naturally arises as result of composition, and the combination of fundamental experiences is discussed in light of our framework (Section 5). This new perspective of scientific models of consciousness invokes pure mathematical entities, avoiding any ontological claim of their physical substrates (Section 6).

2. Category Theory and Process Theory

In this section, we briefly introduce the basic notions of Category theory [16,17], process theory [11] and graphical calculus [18].

2.1. Preliminaries

Category
A category C consists of:
  • a class of objects o b ( C ) ;
  • for each pair of objects A , B , a set C ( A , B ) of morphisms from A to B;
  • for each triple of objects A , B , C , a composition map
    C ( B , C ) × C ( A , B ) C ( A , C ) ( g , f ) g f ;
  • for each object A, an identity morphism 1 A C ( A , A ) ,
satisfying the following axioms:
  • associativity: for any f C ( A , B ) , g C ( B , C ) , h C ( C , D ) , there holds ( h g ) f = h ( g f ) ;
  • identity law: for any f C ( A , B ) , 1 B f = f = f 1 A .
A morphism f C ( A , B ) is an isomorphism if there exists a morphism g C ( B , A ) such that g f = 1 A and f g = 1 B . A product category A × B can be defined componentwise by two categories A and B .
Functor
Given categories C and D , a functor F : C D consists of:
  • a mapping
    o b ( C ) o b ( D ) A F ( A ) ;
  • for each pair of objects A , B of C , a map
    C ( A , B ) D ( F ( A ) , F ( B ) ) f F ( f ) ,
satisfying the following axioms:
  • preserving composition: for any morphisms f C ( A , B ) , g C ( B , C ) , there holds F ( g f ) = F ( g ) F ( f ) ;
  • preserving identity: for any object A of C , F ( 1 A ) = 1 F ( A ) .
A functor F : C D is faithful (full) if for each pair of objects A , B of C , the map
C ( A , B ) D ( F ( A ) , F ( B ) ) f F ( f )
is injective (surjective).
A bifunctor (also called binary functor) is just a functor whose domain is the product of two categories.
Natural Transformation
Let F , G : C D be two functors. A natural transformation τ : F G is a family ( τ A : F ( A ) G ( A ) ) A C of morphisms in D such that the following square commutes:
Entropy 23 00308 i001
for all morphisms f C ( A , B ) . A natural isomorphism is a natural transformation where each of the τ A is an isomorphism.
Strict Monoidal Category
A strict monoidal category consists of:
  • a category C ;
  • a unit object I o b ( C ) ;
  • a bifunctor : C × C C ,
satisfying
  • associativity: for each triple of objects A , B , C of C , A ( B C ) = ( A B ) C ; for each triple of morphisms f , g , h of C , f ( g h ) = ( f g ) h ;
  • unit law: for each object A of C , A I = A = I A ; for each morphism f of C , f 1 I = f = 1 I f .
Strict Symmetric Monoidal Category
A strict monoidal category C is symmetric if it is equipped with a natural isomorphism
σ A , B : A B B A
for all objects A , B , C of C satisfying:
σ B , A σ A , B = 1 A B , σ A , I = 1 A , ( 1 B σ A , C ) ( σ A , B 1 C ) = σ A , B C .
Strict Monoidal Functor
Given two strict monoidal categories C and D , a strict monoidal functor F : C D is a functor F : C D such that F ( A ) F ( B ) = F ( A B ) , F ( f ) F ( g ) = F ( f g ) , F ( I C ) = I D , for any objects A , B of C , and any morphisms f C ( A , A 1 ) , g C ( B , B 1 ) .
A strict symmetric monoidal functor F is a strict monoidal functor that preserves symmetrical structures, i.e., F ( σ A , B ) = σ F ( A ) , F ( B ) . The definition of a general (non-strict) symmetric monoidal functor can be found in [17].
Strict Compact Closed Category
A strict compact closed category is a strict symmetric monoidal category C such that for each object A of C , there exists a object A * and two morphisms
ϵ A : A A * I , η A : I A * A
satisfying:
( ϵ A 1 A ) ( 1 A η A ) = 1 A , ( 1 A * ϵ A ) ( η A 1 A * ) = 1 A * .
A strict compact closed category is called self-dual if A = A * for each object A [19].

2.2. Process Theory

Process theory is an abstract framework of how things happen, be they mental or physical and regardless of their nature. Process theory describes how processes are composed. It has been widely used in various research fields such as the foundations of physical theories [20], quantum theory [19,21], causal models [22,23], relativity [24] and interestingly also natural language [25] and cognition [26,27]. In common with all theories, process theory has its own assumptions, albeit with the advantage that its major feature is that it contains minimal assumptions.
In process theory, we first assume an event occurs, i.e., a change from something typed as A to something typed as B. This is called a process and denoted as a box:
Entropy 23 00308 i002
Second, we assume somethings happen sequentially, such as a process g happens before another process f:
Entropy 23 00308 i003
f happens after g can be seen as a single process from type C to type B, which is denoted by f g : C B . This is called sequential composition. As such, three things happening in sequence is seen as one process without any ambiguity, i.e., the sequential composition of processes is associative: ( f g ) h = f ( g h ) . We also assume that for each type A, there exists a process called the identity 1 A , which does nothing at all to A. This is depicted as a straight line:
Entropy 23 00308 i004
As a consequence, given a process f : A B , we have 1 B f = f = f 1 A .
Third, we assume that there should be different processes happening simultaneously. Two processes f and g that happen simultaneously are described as:
Entropy 23 00308 i005
If we view two types, say A and C, as a single type which we denote as A C , then the simultaneous processes f and g is a single process from type A C to type B D , that we denote as f g : A C B D . We call this a parallel composition of processes.
The above depiction of f g is asymmetric: f on the left while g on the right. This is due to the limitation of a planar drawing. If we want two processes that occur simultaneously placed in a symmetric way, it would mean that if we swap their positions, they should be essentially the same where all the types should match. This can be realised by adding a swap process:
Entropy 23 00308 i006
such that
Entropy 23 00308 i007
With these basic assumptions, processes can be organised into what is called a process theory in the framework of a strict symmetric monoidal category (SMC). A much more detailed description of process theory can be found in [19].
To relate sequential and paralell composition in a simple way, one can add the compact structure to the process theory by using caps Entropy 23 00308 i008 and cups Entropy 23 00308 i009, so that:
Entropy 23 00308 i010
Mathematically speaking, we now have a compact closed category.
As introduced above, process theory focuses on the processes instead of the objects/types, providing a philosophical advantage: process theories emphasise transformations, avoiding any ontological claim or substance-like description of invariant properties of those types, like mass and charge.

2.3. Fine-Grained Version of Process Theory

In general process theory, most of the boxes (processes) are unspecified in the sense that what is inside a box is unknown, whereas we need to know more details about their interactions in some applications. In other words, we need a fine-grained version of process theory. The typical way to derive such a version is to generate all the processes by a set of basic processes called generators, while specifying those generators in terms of equations of processes composed of generators. Below, we illustrate this idea by a typical example called ZX-calculus.
ZX-calculus is a process theory invented by Bob Coecke and Ross Duncan as a graphical language for a pair of complementary quantum processes (represented by two diagrams called green spider and red spider respectively) [18]. All the processes in ZX-calculus are diagrams composed sequentially or in parallel, either of green spiders with phase parameters, red spiders with phase parameters, straight lines, swaps, caps or cups.
These generators satisfy a set of diagrammatic equations called rewriting rules: one can rewrite each diagram into an equivalent one by replacing a part of the diagram which is on one side of an equation with the diagram on the other side of the equation. All the ZX diagrams modulo (modulo means using an equivalent relation) and the rewriting rules form a self-dual compact closed category [18]. To guarantee that there are no conflicts in this rewriting system, ZX-calculus needs a property called soundness: there exists a standard interpretation from the category of ZX diagrams to the category of matrices, i.e., a symmetric monoidal functor between them [18]. More general, a sound rewriting system means that there are not internal contradictions, while completeness would mean that we can prove anything that is right about the phenomena in question with the chosen system. A sound and complete rewriting system defines a unique set of generators.

3. Compositional Approach For Consciousness-Only

In this section, we motivate and explain the concepts of consciousness as fundamental and also the structure for consciousness given by the Yogacara School.

3.1. Process Theory for Consciousness

In any attempt to model consciousness, we expect to fulfill at least three theoretical requirements. First, one would like a theory with a basic and minimum set of assumptions. Process theory seems to fit with that requirement. Symmetric monoidal categories start from a minimum and specific intuitive form to deal with compositions, sequential and parallel. In the rest of this work, we will assume that this minimal structure already convey part of the experience structure. This assumption is partially justified in the fact that, despite a unified experience, we only experience things happening in sequence (one after the other, time) or in parallel (side by side, space).
Second, one would expect those minimum assumptions to be explicit. In other words, we need to model the nature of consciousness from explicit, primitive and axiomatic principles. Process theory in particular, and category theory in general, provides us with an exceptionally well suited mathematics for such axiomatic purposes. Due to the minimality of those assumptions, any extra structure to be added to a process theory will also have an explicit mathematical meaning.
Third, one would like to recover and describe important properties of consciousness from those basic and explicit axioms. Specifically, we would like to recover the unity of consciousness. In process theory, compositionality outlines any unity as a non-trivially composition of some basic processes [10,11]. Unity is formed by sequential and parallel compositions of primary processes. Due to this foundational aspect, compositionality may be a convenient way to target the unity of consciousness, by modelling the unity of experience inside a process theory (Section 5).

3.2. Consciousness as Fundamental

Natural science has achieved great success in modern age, behind which there lies a basic assumption that everything is made of physical objects whose existence is independent of any consciousness. This assumption is so powerful that renders scientific theories not too complicated and allows science results to be tested by independent experiments. However, such objective existence can never be verified by conscious agents, since most cognitive activity is done through consciousness [28], thus the assumption is totally suspended.
Objectivity relates to a perceived or unperceived object, while subjectivity to a perceiving subject. In a everyday understanding of the terms, the object is meant to exist independently of any subject to perceive it (ontology), and as such, objectivity is commonly associated with concepts like truth and reliability (epistemic) [29,30], e.g., the visible wavelength of light range from 700 nm to 400 nm. Contrary, subjectivity seems always interdependent, it involves both perceived and perceiving aspects, making subjective properties dependent of others interactions (internal or external to the subject) and thereof co-dependent [12]. We can further distinguish between epistemic subjectivity, i.e., claims not verifiable (e.g., the claim that red is more beautiful than green), and ontological subjectivity [30]: subjective modes of existence, such as pain or “redness” experienced only by the subject.
In order to understand our point of departure, we first need to recognize that objectivity is an assumption of basic science. The assumption of objectivity as primitive or fundamental is deeply grounded in neuroscience, as well as other scientific fields [31,32,33]. Taking that assumption, one would expect that the subjective aspects of the experience may naturally emerge from the interaction and combination of physical objective entities. For example, contemporary theories of consciousness tend to focus on the physical atomic parts from which, for instance, the unity of experience would emerge as a whole. The parts are considered cells, neurons, brain regions, and the whole being the unified conscious experience. This is called building blocks models [2] or reductionist approaches [32]. This approach, however, leads to the hard problem of consciousness [2,34,35]: since each neuron is composed of basic physical objects–atoms, and they are radically different from consciousness in that they lack key features of the latter like self-awareness and unity [2,3], no matter how complicated the interaction of these physical parts could be, how can those key features of consciousness arise from them? At this point, we consider the reader is familiar enough with this problem, so that we can avoid any deeper introduction.
An alternative assumption is to treat conscious experience as primary, or fundamental process of nature. We assume that all primary objects are indeed conscious-dependent. Treating conscious experience as primary convey two possible interpretations: (i) ontological, i.e., the nature/existence of consciousness is fundamental (substance), (ii) epistemic, i.e., the nature of knowledge about the world is limited by our experience. In this line of thoughts “our knowledge is limited to the realm of our own subjective impressions, allowing us no knowledge of objective reality in and of itself” [9,29]. In this paper, we are neutral about what is the optimal interpretation. Independently, we emphasize that conscious experience is a primary process of nature, a transformation. Being fundamental would also means that there is not further explanation. Therefore, physical objects would be the result of consciousness transforming and everything considered, affirmed or denied, even the idea of objectivity, would occur to us only in consciousness.
Although the new assumption dissolves or evades the hard problem of consciousness, it comes with what we call the dual problem of consciousness: the question about how the objective realm arise from subjective one. To deal with that problem and model conscious experience from the assumption of the primacy of consciousness, we take inspiration from the Eastern philosophy known as Yogacara.

3.3. Yogacara Philosophy

The reason why we choose the Yogacara philosophy and its phenomenology is mainly because it has an explicit description of a structure of eight types of consciousnesses and the relation between consciousness and the physical world. Moreover, the key feature of the Yogacara philosophy is consciousness-only which means there is nothing outside of all sentient beings’ consciousnesses. In modern words, consciousness-only would be better understood as a claim of awareness-only, or perception-only, much closer to modern phenomenology [5,36,37].
The Yogacara philosophy has a rich system of eight consciousnesses consisting of: the first seven consciousnesses—the five sense-consciousnesses (eye or visual, ear or auditory, nose or olfactory, tongue or gustatory, body or tactile consciousnesses), mental consciousness (the sixth consciousness), manas consciousness (the seventh or thought-centre consciousness), and the eighth consciousness—alaya consciousness (storehouse consciousness). These eight consciousnesses are not independent of each other: “... the Alaya consciousness and the first seven consciousnesses generate each in a steady process and are reciprocally cause and effect” [38]. A clarifying metaphor is to think about the eighth consciousness as the ocean, while the other consciousness are different types of waves in its surface. Neither of them are separated of the others and all consciousness are essentially one.
In this framework, the act of perception of the eighth consciousness (Alaya consciousness) is considered extremely subtle or difficult to perceive [39]. Alaya consciousness is thought to be the seed consciousness, i.e., to contain on its own different potentialities that would engender other complex types of experiences [5,39]. We will approach these potentialities only in relation with other seeds, leaving the types on our process theory for Alaya consciousness unspecified (a future approach may define the internal structure of Alaya taking six features in formal analogy with the seed metaphor from [39]). This might be an economical strategy, since, although this structure is considered the same for all living beings, the input and outputs types for those processes might be species dependent, or even specific to each individual.
Moreover, each consciousness “manifests itself in two functional divisions (bhgas), namely, image and perception, i.e., the object perceived or perceived division and the perceiving faculty or perceiving division (nimittabhaga and darsanabhaga)” [39]. The perceived is related to the object and the perceiving to the subject. In Husserlian phenomenology, this division is extrapolated to what is called Noema versus Noesis distinction [40]. The first division is mostly related to the sixth consciousness and the five perceptual consciousnesses, while the second one with the seventh manas consciousness.
The phenomenon of the physical world and the body which we feel everyday comes from the perceived division of Alaya consciousness: “it transforms internally into seeds and the body provided with organs, and externally into the world receptacle. These things that are its transformations become its own object of perception (dlanzbana)” [38]. The receptacle-world and the Body as part of the perceived division of Alaya consciousness should not be thought of as the physical world and the physical body that we feel in our normal lives, but as being related in that the appearance of the latter is based on the existence of the former. As a consequence, the objectivity of the world comes from the same structure shared by different sentient beings in the perceived division of their Alaya consciousnesses.
In the rest of this work, we will focus on a simple model for the perceived and perceiving division of Alaya consciousness. In order to have a model of this structure, we highlight three key ideas: (i) Alaya consciousness is very subtle and it is only shown before us as co-dependent or interdependent process, (ii) Alaya consciousness is primary/fundamental, from which other consciousness and the physical world may arise, (iii) Specifically, the physical world arise from the perceived division of Alaya consciousness.

4. Compositional Model for Consciousness-Only

After the discussion in Section 3, we now provide a compositional model of consciousness based on the Yogacara philosophy of consciousness-only and a few further assumptions.

4.1. Process Theory for Alaya Consciousness

The first feature of Alaya consciousness is its co-dependence, which means each process of Alaya consciousness is dependent on other processes. The general process theory can not display the other-dependence feature because most of its processes are not specified (see Section 2.3). So we need a fine-grained version of process theory which has generators specified by explicit rewriting rules. We might also choose these generators for non-classical systems. This choice is partially justified by recent models of psychology and cognition that seems to be quantum related [41,42]. Moreover, we also require that any parameter appeared in the theory is not a concrete number, according to the unspecification of the types we discussed above.
Based on the requirements for a fine-grained process theory that are noted in previous sections, we introduce a formalism called qufinite Z X Δ -calculus, which is a generalisation of the normal ZX-calculus [18] regarding the following aspects: (1) a labelled triangle symbol is introduced as a new generator, that’s why there is a Δ in the name of the generalised ZX-calculus, (2) all the qudit ZX-calculus (ZX-calculus for qudits– quantum versions of d-ary digits) are unified in a single framework, (3) the parameters (phases) of normal ZX-calculus are generalised from complex numbers to elements of an arbitrary commutative semiring.
We give the details below of the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus: generators and rewriting rules. Throughout this section, N = { 0 , 1 , 2 , } is the set of natural numbers, 2 d N , ⊕ is the modulo d addition, S is an arbitrary commutative semiring [43]. All the diagrams are read from top to bottom as in previous sections.

4.1.1. Generators of Qufinite Z X Δ -Calculus

We give the generators of the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus in Table 1.
Remark 1.
Each input or output of a generator is labeled by a positive integer. For simplicity, the first four generators have each of their inputs and outputs labelled by d, and we just give one label to a wire.
For simplicity, we use the following conventions:
Entropy 23 00308 i012
and
Entropy 23 00308 i013
where 1 d = ( 1 , , 1 ) d 1 ; j { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; k { 1 , , d 1 } ; e d k = ( 0 , , 1 d k , , 0 ) d 1 ; ε represents an empty diagram.
In terms of consciousness interpretation, each generator may be thought as a basic or primary conscious experience. Then, the set of generators becomes a minimal set of experiences. This selection is not unique, unless the group of generators is sound and complete, as we mentioned in Section 2.3.
For example, we may consider that basic conscious experiences involve many inputs and outputs types. This is realized by the many legs on Entropy 23 00308 i014 and Entropy 23 00308 i015. The experience of adding types might be described by Entropy 23 00308 i016 and perhaps primary perception realized by the process Entropy 23 00308 i017. The experience of inverting types might correspond to caps and cups, combinations and segregation experiences may be represented by each of the rhomboids, respectively.
The concrete specification of these or other generators is an empirical task that we left for future works with trained phenomenologists. In our framework, some experiences that are considered basic, such as seeing red or hearing a monotone sound may indeed be the result of composition from our chosen set of generators or another set. This is due to the particular choice we have made. Moreover, one can also choose those monotone experiences (as far as one can give them explicit mathematical meaning) as part of another particular set of generators. The question of what is the unique set of phenomenal generatores is empirical and theoretical issue that may require attentive phenomenology and micro-phenomenological tools. In that case, the goal is to target the soundness and completeness of rewriting systems for conscious experience. Something far beyond the scope of our preliminary attempt.

4.1.2. Rules of Qufinite Z X Δ -Calculus

We provide rewriting rules for qufinite Z X Δ -calculus in Figure 1 and Figure 2. Even though we do not specify which generator corresponds to each basic phenomenal experience, these rules specify the generators in light of what they do regarding each other. Concretely, here we focus on the idea that two or more generators define each other. For example, the green dot Entropy 23 00308 i018 is specified by the rule Entropy 23 00308 i019 = Entropy 23 00308 i020 in the way that it is the only green spider which has no input and one output and can be copied by the red spider Entropy 23 00308 i021. Moreover, the red spider Entropy 23 00308 i021 is also specified by the effects in the green dot Entropy 23 00308 i018. It means that the experience of A, only makes sense if there is another experience B, from which one has a relationship with the other. For instance, the experience of the colour red only make sense if there is another experience of colour, for example, green and blue, otherwise there is not such colour experience at all, or at least, it is of very different nature (e.g., colour blindness). This is understood as a kind of contextual character of conscious phenomena, a particular aspect of experience.
These rewriting rules become the axioms regarding a group of primary experiences, and further ways to define the generators in relation with their consciousness interpretation. In the example above, the red spider with many legs may convey the experience of copy the experience from the green one. Again, specific phenomenal interpretations are left for future works, while we focus here on the introduction of the main concepts and the mathematical machinery.
Additionally, in order to form a compact closed category of diagrams, we also need the following structural rules:
Entropy 23 00308 i022
Entropy 23 00308 i023
where
Entropy 23 00308 i024
is an arbitrary diagram in the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus.
The first two diagrams in Equation (1) mean the cap η s and the cup ϵ s are symmetric, while the last diagram means the connected cap and cup can be yanked. The first two diagrams of Equation (2) mean any diagram could move across a line freely, representing the naturality of the swap morphism. The last diagram of Equation (2) means the swap morphism is self-inverse. Note that now we have a self-dual compact structure rather than a general compact structure, which makes representation of diagrams much easier.
From the rewriting rules noted above, we form a strict self-dual compact closed category Z of ZX diagrams. The objects of Z are all the positive integers, and the monoidal product on these objects are multiplication of integer numbers. Denote the set of generators listed in Table 1 as G. Let Z [ G ] be a free monoidal category generated by G in the following way—(i) any two diagrams D 1 and D 2 are placed side-by-side with D 1 on the left of D 2 to form the monoidal product on morphisms D 1 D 2 , or (ii) the outputs of D 1 connect with the inputs of D 2 when their types all match to each other to form the sequential composition of morphisms D 2 D 1 . The empty diagram is a unit of parallel composition and the diagram of a straight line is a unit of the sequential composition. Denote the set of rules listed in Figure 1 and Figure 2, Equations (1) and (2) by R. One can check that rewriting one diagram to another diagram according to the rules of R is an equivalence relation on diagrams in Z [ G ] . We also call this equivalence as R, then the quotient category Z = Z [ G ] / R is a strict self-dual compact closed category. The qufinite Z X Δ -calculus is seen as a graphical calculus based on the category Z .

4.2. Standard Interpretation of Qufinite Z X Δ -Calculus

To ensure that qufinite Z X Δ -calculus is sound, we need to test its rules in a preexisting reliable system which we now describe. These interpretations, however, does not represent the explicit meaning in terms of our consciousness processes. They are given here to test soundness.
Let Mat S be the category whose objects are non-zero natural numbers and whose morphisms M : m n are n × m matrices taking values in a given commutative semiring S . The composition is matrix multiplication, the monoidal product on objects and morphisms are multiplication of natural numbers and the Kronecker product of matrices respectively. Then Mat S is a strict self-dual compact closed category. We give a standard interpretation, namely · , for the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus diagrams in Mat S :
Entropy 23 00308 i025
where s , t N { 0 } ; i | = ( 0 , , 1 i + 1 , , 0 ) d ; | i = ( ( 0 , , 1 i + 1 , , 0 ) d ) T ; i { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; and [ r ] is the integer part of a real number r.
One can verify that the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus is sound in the sense that for any two diagrams D 1 , D 2 Z , D 1 = D 2 must imply that D 1 = D 2 . This standard interpretation · is actually a strict symmetric monoidal functor from Z to Mat S .
According the standard interpretation, if S is the field of complex numbers, then the green spider corresponds to the computational basis | i } i = 0 d 1 , with d 1 phase angles. The red spider corresponds to the Fourier basis coming from Fourier transformation of the computational basis, up to a global scalar. The red d j diagram represents the j-th unitary which is also a permutation matrix, with j ranging from 0 to d. The triangle diagram labelled with d acts as a successor of phase parameters (adding 1’s to them). The two trapezium diagrams represent unitaries between the Hilbert space of H s H t and the Hilbert space H s t , these two diagrams are invertible to each other.

4.3. The Perceived Division of Alaya Consciousness

Now, we model the perceived division of Alaya consciousness. As we have introduced in Section 3.3, the content of the perceived version of Alaya consciousness is the phenomenon of the physical world and the body which is supposed to have the same mathematical structure for all sentient beings in this world (not necessarily the same types, which may bring specificity and a treatment for individuality). Since each physical object is supposed to be composed of quantum systems, the perceived version of Alaya consciousness is modelled here by the category FdHilb : the category whose objects are all finite dimensional complex Hilbert spaces and whose morphisms are linear maps between the Hilbert spaces with ordinary composition of linear maps as compositions of morphisms. The usual Kronecker tensor product is the monoidal tensor, and the field of complex numbers C (which is a one-dimensional Hilbert space over itself) is the tensor unit. FdHilb is the category of quantum processes which composes the physical world. Since the body is a part of the physical world, the body part of the perceived division of alaya consciousness may be modelled by a subcategory of FdHilb .

4.4. The Perceiving Division of Alaya Consciousness

The function of the perceiving division of Alaya consciousness is to perceive the perceived division, which means a perceiving action from the subject (perceiving) to the object (perceived) of the Alaya consciousness. Since a functor is a structure preserving map or transformation from one category to another one, our first attempt is to model the perceiving division of Alaya consciousness by a functor from Z to FdHilb . This functor is set up as a modification of the standard interpretation functor · , i.e.,: just choose a semiring homomorphism f from S to C and let { | i } i = 0 d 1 a standard basis of a Hilbert space with dimension d, then replace a i with f ( a i ) in the codomain of the interpretation · . One can check that a monoidal functor is obtained in this way, where a semiring homomorphism from S to C is selected.

5. The Unity of Experience

As a consequence of our first simple approach to model conscious experience, we consider the combination problem of the unity of experience.
We suggest that some aspects of Alaya consciousness can be modelled by qufinite Z X Δ -calculus, making it a serious and somewhat justified attempt. A general diagram represents some primary conscious experience and a diagram with outputs but without inputs represent a state of consciousness. Sequential composition of two diagrams represents two successive conscious processes happening one after the another, while parallel composition of two diagrams represents two conscious processes happening simultaneously. These processes may compound to generate more complex experiences.
Our approach is an alternative to conserve the irreducible and fundamental nature of experience. It is not, however, the only one. Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism, among others philosophies, also consider experience seriously, but these two assigns a quantifiable character to that experience. According to these views, consciousness is present in all fundamental physical entities [44] and the composition of basic blocks of experience creates our conscious experience.
Nevertheless, an important question remains for those irreductible attemps: How “microphenomenal seeds of consciousness” constitute macrophenomenal conscious experiences as we experience them?—the so-called combination problem for Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism [45]. This problem convey an specific form of the hard problem of consciousness, i.e., how could the key features of consciousness, like its unity, arise from any kind of interactions of physical atomic experiences (given by physical theory of your choice), no matter how many of these atoms and how complicated the interactions are, which have none of those key features? [2,34,35]. In other words, how these building blocks of experience compound one single unified macro phenomenal subjective experience [3]: the phenomenal unity of experience [3,46]. In Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism, the dualism between mind and matter is now replaced by two modes, micro and macro experience, of the same ontology.
Remarkable, the combination problem has three aspects [45]: structural, subject and quality. Each one of these aspects leads to a specific sub-problem. On the one hand, the structure of the micro world, mostly associated with quantum mechanics, gives the impression of being different from the structure of macro experiences. This is the structural mismatch problem, which also appears between macro experience structure and macro physical structures in the brain [45]. On the other hand, there is the question of how micro subject combine to give rise to macro subjects, and how micro qualities combine to give macro qualities. It seems that no group of micro subjects need the existence of a macro subject, and additionally, it is not clear how possible limited micro qualities yield to the many macro qualities that can be experienced, including different colors, shapes, sounds, smells, and tastes (for detail see [45]). According to Chalmers, a satisfactory solution of the combination problem must face all these three aspects.
Our framework targets all of these aspects of the combination problem. First, the mathematical structure of the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus for Alaya consciousness is a unification of all dimensional qudit ZX-calculus. If generators are interpreted in Hilbert space, the latest becomes a graphical language for quantum theory. This means that the Z X Δ -calculus for conscious processes shares a similar structure to quantum theory (please note that a similar structure means similar mathematical relationships, i.e., two very different phenomena in nature may share the same structure and being modelled by the same equations, or more generally, the same categories). This similarity solves the mismatch at the level of micro experience, without any ontological commitment to quantum particles (e.g., different to Hameroff and Penrose model [47]). At the level of macro experiences we avoid any match or mismatch with macro physical structures because the model does not reduce experience to neural events (non-isomorphic relationship). It means that conscious experience does not need to share the same structure that classical neurons. Second, the model does not distinguish between subject and quality, everything is a conscious process, a conscious experience. Those fundamental conscious processes of reality, namely the generators of the theory, compound other conscious processes just by means of connecting them together: via sequential and parallel composition. The result of those compositions are other more complex subjective and qualitative processes. New compounded processes depend on the basic generators, while the generators are interrelated to define themselves via rewriting rules (axioms), representing more complex experiential relationships; i.e., each process need other processes to specify itself.
In our framework, unity of consciousness is naturally described as a result of process composition [48]. If someone insists on generators being matched with subjects or agents, then micro subjects (generators) and macro subjects (composition of generators) necessitate themselves as imposed by the co-dependent nature. This deals with the problem of subject/quality composition at the level of Alaya consciousness (please check [45] for details on that problem). This treatment also allows to deal with the combination of specific qualities as the result of compositions in the seventh mental consciousness, work that form part of an ongoing project.
Summarizing, while in Panpsychism the division between micro and macro is given by physical systems (e.g., atoms versus neurons, or neurons versus neural assembles), in our framework there is no such distinction. The distinction just vanish, since we consider generators that already carry the properties of the whole (experience), following the compositionality principle. The choice of generators might seems arbitrary, and it is, as far as we do not have a sound and complete rewriting system for conscious experience.

6. Conclusions

Our framework is based on arbitrary commutative semirings as a compositional model of consciousness, with the emphasis on its potential use for the mathematical and structural studies of consciousness [13,14,15]. We introduced generators and processes as abstract mathematical structures to target some aspects of the conscious experience which are independent of their physical realizations. This introduction is inspired by the Yogacara school of Buddhism and other philosophies assuming that consciousness is primary or fundamental. In this first attempt, we have focused on Alaya consciousness, its co-dependent character and its perceived and perceiving division. It allow us to make a first approach to the dual question of how the objective world emerges from the subjective one.
A future approach may target more details on the internal structure of Alaya consciousness, taking for example, six features in formal analogy with the seed metaphor from [39]. Moreover, we leave for future work the model of mental, manas and the five sense-consciousnesses. In the future, we also expect to generalise the qufinite Z X Δ -calculus to the infinite dimensional case, from which standard quantum mechanics might be recovered. It is to be noted that we have not recovered standard quantum mechanics. To do so would mean generalising our model to derive the standard quantum mechanics described by the Schrödinger equation. This is important in order to give a definitive answer to the dual problem of consciousness introduced above.
Other very interesting models also aim to target that question. For example, the conscious agent model intends to recover fundamental physics from the agent’s interactions, as for instance in quantum mechanics [49]. Sadly, it is not clear that current versions of the conscious agent model are capable of recovering the entire objective realm (see objections and replies section in [49]). In our framework part of the reconstruction goal pursued by the conscious agent model is achieved for free, without overhead, invoking only the simple structure of SMC in relationship with phenomenal aspects. In doing so, our approach to consciousness processes and quantum theory share a similar, but not the same, mathematical structure.
It allows a compositional treatment of the combination problem of basic experience that may give rise to complex ones. One very influential model of consciousness also attempting to target that question is the the integrated information theory (IIT) [50]. This model, however, conveys a Panpsychist view. Unfortunately, the model is not neutral about the physical neural substrate, and although it intends to highlight the primacy of consciousness, in practice, the current version falls in reductive accounts. Such models also claim compositions, but they are not compositional in the sense exposed here. In IIT, the minimal elements of the theory are gates that are not conscious, while consciousness emerges from the right causal combination of these gates (integration). Contrary, compositionality in our sense means that the minimal compositional elements, i.e., generatores, represents already conscious experiences.
Our model, the conscious agent model and IIT, all share the same goal of mathematize phenomenology. Although with different philosophical commitments, the common point of departure is that axioms and postulates consider aspects of consciousness as primary. However, we close by remarking that a process theory for consciousness is not only about modelling consciousness with any type of mathematics (as other models), but about modelling consciousness with category theory in a graphical form, i.e., axiomatic mathematics. This form of mathematics explicitly introduces structures, assumptions and axioms, plus the possibility of compositional treatments. We believe that because being foundational, this approach is better suited to describing the conscious experience as fundamental. Finally, we are hopeful that due to its co-dependent feature, and sufficient generality, our framework may pave the way for further research on the scientific study of conscious experience and its phenomenology.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, C.M.S. and Q.W.; investigation C.M.S., Q.W. and I.K.; writing—original draft preparation, C.M.S.; writing—review and editing, C.M.S., Q.W. and I.K.; visualization, C.M.S. and Q.W. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

C.M.S. is funded by Comisión Nacional de Investigación Ciencia y Tecnología (CONICYT, current ANID) through Programa Formacion de Capital Avanzado (PFCHA), Doctoral scholarship Becas Chile: CONICYT PFCHA/DOCTORADO BECAS CHILE/2016–72170507. Q.W. is supported by AFOSR grant FA2386-18-1-4028. We also acknowledge the grant: Categorical Theories of Consciousness: Bridging Neuroscience and Fundamental Physics (FQXi-RFP-CPW-2018).

Acknowledgments

The authors appreciate valuable feedback and discussions from Bob Coecke, Konstantinos Meichanetzidis and Robert Prentner. The authors would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers and editors for their helpful comments.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Seth, A.K. Consciousness: The last 50 years (and the next). Brain Neurosci. Adv. 2018, 2. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  2. Searle, J.R. Consciousness. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 2000, 23, 557–578. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  3. Bayne, T.; Chalmers, D.J. What is the unity of consciousness? The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration, and Dissociation; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012; pp. 1–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  4. Crick, F.; Koch, C. Consciousness and neuroscience. Cereb. Cortex 1998, 8, 97–1007. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Lusthaus, D. Buddhist Phenomenology, 1st ed.; Routledge Curzon: Oxfordshire, UK, 2002; p. 632. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Makeham, J. Introduction. In Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China; Makeham, J., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Fields, C.; Hoffman, D.D.; Prakash, C.; Singh, M. Conscious agent networks: Formal analysis and application to cognition. Cogn. Syst. Res. 2018, 47, 186–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  8. Thompson, E. Mind in Life; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  9. Varela, F.J. Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem. J. Conscious. Stud. 1996, 3, 330–349. [Google Scholar]
  10. Coecke, B. An Alternative Gospel of Structure: Order, Composition, Processes. In Quantum Physics and Linguistics: A Compositional, Diagrammatic Discourse; Heunen, C., Sadrzadeh, M., Grefenstette, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  11. Coecke, B.; Duncan, R.; Kissinger, A.; Wang, Q. Generalised Compositional Theories and Diagrammatic Reasoning. In Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils. Fundamental Theories of Physics; Chiribella, G., Spekkens, R., Eds.; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2016; Volume 181, pp. 309–366. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  12. Signorelli, C.M.; Meling, D. Towards new concepts for a biological neuroscience of consciousness. Cogn. Neurodynamics 2021. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Prentner, R. Consciousness and topologically structured phenomenal spaces. Conscious. Cogn. 2019, 70, 25–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  14. Yoshimi, J. Mathematizing phenomenology. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2007, 6, 271–291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Tsuchiya, N.; Saigo, H. Applying Yoneda’s lemma to consciousness research: Categories of level and contents of consciousness. Preprint 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Awodey, S. Category Theory, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; p. 266. [Google Scholar]
  17. Maclane, S. Categorical Algebra. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 1965, 71, 40–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  18. Coecke, B.; Duncan, R. Interacting quantum observables: Categorical algebra and diagrammatics. New J. Phys. 2011, 13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Coecke, B.; Kissinger, A. Picturing Quantum Processes. A First Course in Diagrammatic Reasoning; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Coecke, B. (Ed.) New Structures for Physics; Lecture Notes in Physics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2011; Volume 813, p. 1034. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Abramsky, S.; Coecke, B. A categorical semantics of quantum protocols. In Proceedings of the 19th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science (LICS’04), Turku, Finland, 17 July 2004; pp. 415–425. [Google Scholar]
  22. Kissinger, A.; Uijlen, S. A categorical semantics for causal structure. In Proceedings of the 32nd Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science (LICS), Reykjavik, Iceland, 20–23 June 2017; pp. 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  23. Pinzani, N.; Gogioso, S.; Coecke, B. Categorical Semantics for Time Travel. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1902.00032. [Google Scholar]
  24. Kissinger, A.; Hoban, M.; Coecke, B. Equivalence of relativistic causal structure and process terminality. arXiv 2017, arXiv:1708.04118. [Google Scholar]
  25. Coecke, B.; Sadrzadeh, M.; Clark, S. Mathematical Foundations for a Compositional Distributional Model of Meaning. Linguist. Anal. 2010, 36, 345–384. [Google Scholar]
  26. Bolt, J.; Coecke, B.; Genovese, F.; Lewis, M.; Marsden, D.; Piedeleu, R. Interacting Conceptual Spaces I: Grammatical Composition of Concepts. arXiv 2017, arXiv:1708.04118. [Google Scholar]
  27. Signorelli, C.M.; Dundar-Coecke, S.; Wang, V.; Coecke, B. Cognitive Structures of Space-Time. Front. Psychol. 2020. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Signorelli, C.M. Can Computers become Conscious and overcome Humans? Front. Robot. Artif. Intell. 2018, 5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  29. Mulder, D.H. Objectivity. Available online: https://philpapers.org/rec/MULO (accessed on 26 February 2021).
  30. Searle, J.R. How to study consciousness scientifically. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Biol. Sci. 1998, 353, 1935–1942. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  31. Anderson, P.W. More Is Different. Science 1972, 177, 393–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  32. Mazzocchi, F. Complexity in biology. EMBO Rep. 2008, 9, 10–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  33. beim Graben, P. Contextual Emergence in Neuroscience. Closed Loop Neuroscience; Academic Press: Cambridge, CA, USA, 2016; pp. 171–184. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Thomas Nagel. What is it like to be a bat? Philos. Rev. 1974, 83, 435–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Chalmers, D. The puzzle of conscious experience. Sci. Am. 1995, 273, 80–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. LI, J. Buddhist Phenomenology and the Problem of Essence. Comp. Philos. Int. J. Constr. Engagem. Distinct Approaches Towar. World Philos. 2015, 7, 59–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  37. Kern, I. The Structure of Consciousness According to Xuanzang. J. Br. Soc. Phenomenol. 1988. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  38. Xuanzang; Cook, F.H.; Vasubandhu. Three Texts on Consciousness Only; Numata Center for Buddhist Translation and Research: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  39. Xuanzang; TatWei; Vasubandhu. Cheng Wei Shi Lun; The Doctrine of Mere-Consciousness; Ch’eng Wei-shih Lun Publication Committee: Hong Kong, China, 1973. [Google Scholar]
  40. Husserl, E. General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology; Martinus Nijhoff Publishers: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1983. [Google Scholar]
  41. Bruza, P.D.; Wang, Z.; Busemeyer, J.R. Quantum cognition: A new theoretical approach to psychology. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2015, 19, 383–393. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  42. Cervantes, V.H.; Dzhafarov, E.N. Snow queen is evil and beautiful: Experimental evidence for probabilistic contextuality in human choices. Decision 2018, 5, 193–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Golan, J.S. Semirings and their Applications; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1999. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Chalmers, D.J. Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism. Amherst Lect. Philos. 2013, 8. [Google Scholar]
  45. Chalmers, D.J. The Combination Problem for Panpsychism; Brüntrup, G., Jaskolla, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016; pp. 179–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  46. Revonsuo, A.; Newman, J. Binding and consciousness. Conscious. Cogn. 1999, 8, 123–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Hameroff, S.; Penrose, R. Consciousness in the universe: A review of the “Orch OR” theory. Phys. Life Rev. 2014, 11, 39–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  48. Signorelli, C.M.; Wang, Q.; Coecke, B. Reasoning about conscious experience with axiomatic and graphical mathematics. Submitt. Conscious. Cogn. 2021. [Google Scholar]
  49. Hoffman, D.D.; Prakash, C. Objects of consciousness. Front. Psychol. 2014, 5, 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  50. Oizumi, M.; Albantakis, L.; Tononi, G. From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated Information Theory 3.0. PLoS Comput. Biol. 2014, 10, e1003588. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
Figure 1. Qufinite Z X Δ -calculus rules I, where α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; β d = ( b 1 , , b d 1 ) ; α d β d = ( a 1 b 1 , , a d 1 b d 1 ) ; a k , b k S ; k { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; m N .
Figure 1. Qufinite Z X Δ -calculus rules I, where α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; β d = ( b 1 , , b d 1 ) ; α d β d = ( a 1 b 1 , , a d 1 b d 1 ) ; a k , b k S ; k { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; m N .
Entropy 23 00308 g001
Figure 2. Qufinite Z X Δ -calculus rules II, where 1 d = ( 1 , , 1 ) d 1 ; 0 d = ( 0 , , 0 ) d 1 ; α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; β d = ( b 1 , , b d 1 ) ; a k , b k S ; k { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 1 , , d 1 } ; s , t , u N { 0 } .
Figure 2. Qufinite Z X Δ -calculus rules II, where 1 d = ( 1 , , 1 ) d 1 ; 0 d = ( 0 , , 0 ) d 1 ; α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; β d = ( b 1 , , b d 1 ) ; a k , b k S ; k { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 1 , , d 1 } ; s , t , u N { 0 } .
Entropy 23 00308 g002
Table 1. Generators of qufinite Z X Δ -calculus, where m , n N ; α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; a i S ; i { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; s , t N { 0 } .
Table 1. Generators of qufinite Z X Δ -calculus, where m , n N ; α d = ( a 1 , , a d 1 ) ; a i S ; i { 1 , , d 1 } ; j { 0 , 1 , , d 1 } ; s , t N { 0 } .
Entropy 23 00308 i011
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Signorelli, C.M.; Wang, Q.; Khan, I. A Compositional Model of Consciousness Based on Consciousness-Only. Entropy 2021, 23, 308. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/e23030308

AMA Style

Signorelli CM, Wang Q, Khan I. A Compositional Model of Consciousness Based on Consciousness-Only. Entropy. 2021; 23(3):308. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/e23030308

Chicago/Turabian Style

Signorelli, Camilo Miguel, Quanlong Wang, and Ilyas Khan. 2021. "A Compositional Model of Consciousness Based on Consciousness-Only" Entropy 23, no. 3: 308. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/e23030308

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop